翻訳と辞書
Words near each other
・ Sequenceome
・ Sequencer
・ Sequencer (Covenant album)
・ Sequences Art Festival
・ SequenceVariantAnalyzer
・ Sequencia
・ Sequencing
・ Sequencing batch reactor
・ Sequencing by hybridization
・ Sequencing by ligation
・ Sequencing fountain
・ Sequenom
・ Sequent
・ Sequent (disambiguation)
・ Sequent (MUD)
Sequent calculus
・ Sequent Computer Systems
・ Sequentia (music group)
・ Sequential access
・ Sequential access memory
・ Sequential algorithm
・ Sequential analysis
・ Sequential art
・ Sequential bilingualism
・ Sequential Circuits
・ Sequential Circuits Prophet 2000
・ Sequential Circuits Prophet-5
・ Sequential Circuits Six-Trak
・ Sequential Circuits Studio 440
・ Sequential consistency


Dictionary Lists
翻訳と辞書 辞書検索 [ 開発暫定版 ]
スポンサード リンク

Sequent calculus : ウィキペディア英語版
Sequent calculus
Sequent calculus is, in essence, a style of formal logical argumentation where every line of a proof is a conditional tautology (called a sequent by Gerhard Gentzen) instead of an unconditional tautology. Each conditional tautology is inferred from other conditional tautologies on earlier lines in a formal argument according to rules and procedures of inference, giving a better approximation to the style of natural deduction used by mathematicians than David Hilbert's earlier style of formal logic where every line was an unconditional tautology. There may be more subtle distinctions to be made; for example, there may be non-logical axioms upon which all propositions are implicitly dependent. Then sequents signify conditional theorems in a first-order language rather than conditional tautologies.
Sequent calculus is one of several extant styles of proof calculus for expressing line-by-line logical arguments.
* Hilbert style. Every line is an unconditional tautology (or theorem).
* Gentzen style. Every line is a conditional tautology (or theorem) with zero or more conditions on the left.
*
* Natural deduction. Every (conditional) line has exactly one asserted proposition on the right.
*
* Sequent calculus. Every (conditional) line has zero or more asserted propositions on the right.
In other words, natural deduction and sequent calculus systems are particular distinct kinds of Gentzen-style systems. Hilbert-style systems typically have a very small number of inference rules, relying more on sets of axioms. Gentzen-style systems typically have very few axioms, if any, relying more on sets of rules.
Gentzen-style systems have significant practical and theoretical advantages compared to Hilbert-style systems. For example, both natural deduction and sequent calculus systems facilitate the elimination and introduction of universal and existential quantifiers so that unquantified logical expressions can be manipulated according to the much simpler rules of propositional calculus. In a typical argument, quantifiers are eliminated, then propositional calculus is applied to unquantified expressions (which typically contain free variables), and then the quantifiers are reintroduced. This very much parallels the way in which mathematical proofs are carried out in practice by mathematicians. Predicate calculus proofs are generally much easier to discover with this approach, and are often shorter. Natural deduction systems are more suited to practical theorem-proving. Sequent calculus systems are more suited to theoretical analysis.
==Introduction==

In proof theory and mathematical logic, sequent calculus is a family of formal systems sharing a certain style of inference and certain formal properties. The first sequent calculi, systems LK and LJ, were introduced in 1934/1935 by Gerhard Gentzen〔, .〕 as a tool for studying natural deduction in first-order logic (in classical and intuitionistic versions, respectively). Gentzen's so-called "Main Theorem" (''Hauptsatz'') about LK and LJ was the cut-elimination theorem,〔, gives a 5-page proof of the elimination theorem. See also pages 188, 250.〕〔, gives a very brief proof of the cut-elimination theorem.〕 a result with far-reaching meta-theoretic consequences, including consistency. Gentzen further demonstrated the power and flexibility of this technique a few years later, applying a cut-elimination argument to give a (transfinite) proof of the consistency of Peano arithmetic, in surprising response to Gödel's incompleteness theorems. Since this early work, sequent calculi, also called Gentzen systems,〔, calls Gentzen systems LC systems. Curry's emphasis is more on theory than on practical logic proofs.〕〔. This book is much more concerned with the theoretical, metamathematical implications of Gentzen-style sequent calculus than applications to practical logic proofs.〕〔, defines Gentzen systems and proves various theorems within these systems, including Gödel's completeness theorem and Gentzen's theorem.〕〔, gives a brief theoretical presentation of Gentzen systems. He uses the tableau proof layout style.〕 and the general concepts relating to them, have been widely applied in the fields of proof theory, mathematical logic, and automated deduction.

抄文引用元・出典: フリー百科事典『 ウィキペディア(Wikipedia)
ウィキペディアで「Sequent calculus」の詳細全文を読む



スポンサード リンク
翻訳と辞書 : 翻訳のためのインターネットリソース

Copyright(C) kotoba.ne.jp 1997-2016. All Rights Reserved.